University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School
Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository
All Faculty Scholarship Faculty Works
2009
Moral Judgment and Moral Heuristics in Breach of Contract Moral Judgment and Moral Heuristics in Breach of Contract
Tess Wilkinson-Ryan
University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School
Author ORCID Identi;er:
Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship
Part of the Commercial Law Commons, Contracts Commons, Law and Economics Commons, and the
Law and Psychology Commons
Repository Citation Repository Citation
Wilkinson-Ryan, Tess, "Moral Judgment and Moral Heuristics in Breach of Contract" (2009).
All Faculty
Scholarship
. 2573.
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship/2573
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Works at Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship
Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in All Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Penn
Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact biddlerepos@law.upenn.edu.
1
Moral Judgment and Moral Heuristics in Breach of Contract
ABSTRACT
Most people think that breaking a promise is immoral, and that a breach of contract is a
kind of broken promise. However, the law does not explicitly recognize the moral context of
breach of contract. Using a series of web-based questionnaires, we asked subjects to read breach
of contract cases and answer questions about the legal, financial, and moral implications of each
case. Our results suggest that people are quite sensitive to the moral dimensions of a breach of
contract, especially the perceived intentions of the breacher. In the first study, we framed the
motivation for a contractor’s breach as either the chance to make more money or the chance to
avoid losing money. Subjects were more punitive when the motivation appeared to be greed
(breach to gain) than when the motivation appeared to be fear (breach to avoid loss). In the
second study, we manipulated the timing of the negotiation over damages, comparing cases in
which the promisor asks to negotiate damages before definitively breaching (as in a liquidated
damages clause) with cases in which the breach has already occurred. We predicted that once the
contract is breached, the moral violation becomes very salient, and we found that subjects were
less punitive when they setting damages ex ante. Finally, results from the third study suggest that
subjects seemed to believe that intentionally breaking a contractual promise is a punishable
moral harm in itself. When presented with identical losses, one from an intentional breach of
contract and the other from a negligent tort, subjects were more punitive toward the breacher
than the negligent tortfeasor. They treated willful breach as an intentional harm.
2
Moral Judgment and Moral Heuristics in Breach of Contract
Tess Wilkinson-Ryan, J.D., M.A.
Penn Faculty Fellow, University of Pennsylvania Law School
Jonathan Baron, Ph.D.
Professor of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania
Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, forthcoming
INTRODUCTION
Most people agree that breaking a promise is immoral. Because the legal construct of
contract is tied so closely to the moral notion of a promise, breach of contract would seem to fall
into the same category of moral harm as a broken promise. However, the law does not explicitly
recognize the moral context of breach of contract. The penalty for breach of contract is limited
(with some exceptions) to money damages in the amount necessary to put the non-breaching
party in as good a position as he would have been in had the contract been performed.
1
In
contract, a damages award does not depend on the reason for breach, and there are no punitive
damages for intentional breach of contract.
2
This means that there are no legal distinctions
between cases that elicit very different moral intuitions; morally salient factors like the motives
and intentions of the breacher are legally irrelevant. Though this may seem straightforward to
lawyers and academics, many people find this rule at odds with the idea of the moral obligation
of a contract. In this paper, we argue that commonsense notions of contract and promise find
1
RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 264
2
E. ALLEN FARNSWORTH, Contracts § 12.3 (3
rd
ed. 1999) (“The principal interest protected by
that law is the expectation interest, measured by the amount of money required to put the injured
party in as good a position as that party would have been in had the contract been performed…
‘Willful’ breaches should not be distinguished from other breaches.”)
3
contract law generally counter-intuitive and efficient breach downright objectionable. Not only
does our legal system appear indifferent to a moral harm (breaking a promise), it permits
breachers to profit from a moral violation. Here, we ask when laypeople consider breach to be
immoral, which moral principles and moral heuristics they employ to make that judgment, and to
what extent their moral reasoning affects their legal and financial decision-making.
Our results suggest that people are quite sensitive to the moral dimensions of a breach of
contract. Subjects evaluated a series of breach of contract cases, and we asked them to set
damages awards and to answer questions about the moral culpability of the actors. In the first
study, we framed the motivation for a contractor’s breach as either the chance to make more
money or the chance to avoid losing money. Subjects were more punitive when the motivation
appeared to be greed (breach to gain) than when the motivation appeared to be fear (breach to
avoid loss). Subjects indicated that punitive damages were appropriate for the intentional, greedy
breacher. We also manipulated the timing of the breach, comparing cases in which the promisor
asks to negotiate damages before definitively breaching with cases in which the breach is a fait
accompli. We predicted that once the contract is breached, the moral violation becomes very
salient. In fact, subjects suggested a lower penalty for breach when they setting damages ex ante.
Finally, subjects appeared to equate willful breach of contract with intentional harm. They set the
damages for willful breach of contract at a higher level than the same loss caused by negligence.
I. NORMATIVE AND DESCRIPTIVE THEORIES OF MORALITY IN CONTRACT
Damages for breach of contract are measured in terms of the promisee’s subjective
expected benefit.
3
In a breach of contracts case, the " victim"/promisee is awarded the full value
of the benefit of the contract, so her interests are actually advanced to the point that they would
3
RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 344; FARNSWORTH, supra note 4, § 12.1.
4
have been had the contract been completed, not simply returned to their ex ante position, as in a
torts case.
4
However, punitive damages are not awarded in contracts, though consequential
damages are a permitted in the event that the breach has caused other losses to the promisee.
5
Specific performance is rarely awarded, and is reserved for the few cases in which money
damages would be unable to redress the promisee's interests.
6
Under these rules, the breacher's
motivation for the breach is mostly irrelevant. There are no legal differences between a case in
which a job becomes unprofitable (say, due to a rise in the cost of materials) and a case in which
a job becomes less appealing due to a more lucrative offer elsewhere
7
, though we will offer data
to suggest that most people make a moral distinction between these cases.
Economic theory supports the rule of expectation damages, which arguably provides
optimal incentives for efficient contracts (and efficient breaches).
8
It is not worth it to the
promisor to breach the contract unless the cost of performance exceeds the benefit of
performance to the promisee. That is, the promisor's own self-interested calculation of costs and
4
FARNSWORTH, supra note 4, §12.1.
5
FARNSWORTH, supra note 4, § 12.9.
6
Id. at § 12.6 (“[E]quitable relief would not be granted if the legal remedy of damages was
adequate to protect the injured party.”) See also, T. Anthony Kronman, Specific Performance. 45
U. CHI. L. REV. 351, 365 (1978) (arguing that the adequacy test for money damages “draws the
line between specific performance and money damages in the way that most contracting parties
would draw it were they free to make their own rules concerning remedies for breach and had
they deliberated about the matter at the time of contracting.”)
7
See Globe Ref. Co. v. Landa Cotton Oil Co., 190 U.S. 540, 544 (1903) (in which Holmes notes
that “if a contract is broken the measure of damages generally is the same, whatever the cause of
the breach.”) Damages in contract are meant to be compensatory, not punitive. See FARNSWORTH
§ 12.8 (“it is a fundamental tenet of the law of contract remedies that an injured party should not
be put in a better position than had the contract been performed.”) For a judicial argument in
favor of the efficiency of this position, see Patton v. Mid-Continent Sys., 841 F.2d 74f2 (7
th
Cir.
1988) (in which Judge Posner argues that “even if the breach is deliberate, it is not necessarily
blameworthy. The promisor may simply have discovered that his performance is worth more to
someone else. If so, efficiency is promoted by allowing him to break his promise, provided he
makes good the promisee’s actual losses.”)
8
See, e.g., RICHARD POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW ch. 4 (3
rd
ed. 1986); STEVEN
SHAVELL, FOUNDATIONS OF THE ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW, 2004.
5
benefits of breach integrates the benefit of the contract to the promisee. This forces the promisor
to internalize the costs of breach to both parties, and encourages the promisor only to breach in
cases in which the breach would be overall welfare-maximizing. Were the damages set at a lower
level, the promisor might have an incentive to breach more often and in cases in which the
overall welfare of the parties would not be maximized via a breach. If the damages are set at a
higher level, or if specific performance is required, promisors may be deterred from breaching in
cases in which the cost of performance is higher than the value of the performance to the
promisee, which is inefficient on its face. In addition, a higher level of damages increases the
promisor's risk; some contractors may be unwilling to pay extra to compensate for this risk, so
that contracts that could benefit both parties would not be made.
Of course, there may still be sound moral arguments against efficient breach. The
traditional moral view holds that a contract is a promise, and that breaking a promise is immoral.
The promise theory of contract relies on the underlying autonomy of individuals insofar as they
can choose to obligate themselves in such a way that courts must respect (e.g., enforce) their
self-imposed obligation.
9
Under this theory, expectation damages are justified based on the
freely-undertaken promise.
10
The moral view of contracts seems to be in line with common
notions about what it means to make a promise. However, even the promise theory does not
argue with expectation damages as the correct remedy for breach of contract. We will present
evidence that many people find expectation damages inadequate to remedy an intentional breach.
Norms, Schemas, and the Psychological Contract
The sanctity of a promise is an unusually resonant moral principle. Cultural psychologists
9
See FRIED, supra note 1.
10
Id. at 18-20.
6
have identified the rule of contract as one of only three universal moral norms.
11
In economics
experiments, subjects who are otherwise willing to lie about their intentions in a cooperation
game can be trusted to keep their word if they have explicitly promised, even without threat of
sanctions.
12
Our prediction is that people hold such strong beliefs about the moral rules of
promise and contract that they will use these rules to inform their legal decision-making.
When a contract is incomplete or informal, people use their own ethical principles to fill
in the spaces. Stuart Macaulay reported in 1963 that many, if not most, businessmen actually had
a preference for relying on “common honesty and decency” or industry and social norms rather
than formal contracts.
13
“Commitments are to be honored in almost all situations; one does not
welsh on a deal.”
14
More recently, behavioral researchers have begun to elaborate on the notion
of what it means to honor a commitment. Sandra Robinson and Denise Rousseau introduced the
concept of the “psychological contract,” a construct meant to encompass the beliefs or
perceptions of the parties about the conditions of a reciprocal exchange.
15
This is particularly apt
in the employment context, their primary focus, because even when a written employment
contract exists, it is unlikely to iterate the various contributions, obligations, and inducements
that characterize an employer/employee relationship over time. Robinson and Rousseau found
that perceived violations of the psychological contract have real effects for employers, including
higher turnover and lower employee satisfaction. Like Macaulay’s study, their research suggests
11
Paul Robinson, Robert Kurzban & Owen Jones, The Origins of Shared Intuitions of Justice, 16
VAND. L. REV. 1633 (2007).
12
Robyn Dawes, Jeanne McTavish & Harriet Shaklee, Behavior, Communication, and
Assumptions about Other People’s Behavior in a Common Dilemma Situation, 35 J.
PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCH. 1 (1977).
13
Stewart Macaulay, Non-Contractual Relations in Business: A Preliminary Study, 28 AM. SOC.
REV. 55 (1963).
14
Id. at 63.
15
Sandra L. Robinson & Denise M. Rousseau, Violating the Psychological Contract: Not the
Exception but the Norm, 15 J. ORG. BEH. 245. (1994).
7
that parties look to moral norms governing the unwritten contract to define the notion of
performance and breach.
In the case that the contract is formal and adequate to the situation, lay intuitions are still
relevant in how people interpret its terms. Dennis Stolle and Andrew Slain studied the effects of
exculpatory clauses in contracts on consumer behavior.
16
They found that exculpatory language
in a standard form contract had a deterrent effect on subjects’ likelihood to seek compensation,
even when it is not clear that the exculpatory clause would be legally enforceable. Parties’ beliefs
about the contract were informed by the terms of the contract itself as well as their intuitions or
beliefs about contracts in general, namely, that they are enforceable as written. In this study, we
are extending these questions about contract schemas into the domain of the remedy for breach
of contract, asking how people define the contractual obligation and what they require for
compensation.
Moral Heuristics in Contract
People’s beliefs about contracts are affected by their moral intuitions, even when those
intuitions are inconsistent or unreasonable. Cass Sunstein has recently catalogued a partial list of
moral heuristics—short-cuts, or rules of thumb—that people use in order to make moral
judgments.
17
A heuristic need not be normatively wrong in an absolute sense; rather, heuristics
are just simple rules, often rules that are useful in most of the cases in which they apply.
Nonetheless, as Sunstein argues, moral judgments based on these kinds of rules of thumb may be
less sound than moral judgments that result from deliberative reasoning.
18
In this paper, we will
16
Dennis P. Stolle & Andrew J. Slain, Standard Form Contracts and Contract Schemas: A
Preliminary Investigation of the Effects of Exculpatory Clauses on Consumers’ Propensity to
Sue, 15 BEH. SCIENCES AND THE LAW 83 (1997).
17
Cass Sunstein, Moral Heuristics, 28 BEH. & BRAIN SCIENCES 531 (2005).
18
Id. at 534-535.
8
be considering the kinds of heuristics that might affect moral judgment in the field of contracts.
To the extent that subjects find breach of contract to be morally wrong, prior research
suggests that they will focus on the punishment that the breacher “deserves” rather than the rules
that would create the most efficient incentives. The rule of expectation damages and efficient
breach sets optimal economic incentives for the making and breaking of contracts. However, we
know that people are often insensitive to these kinds of incentives, especially when the incentive
structure fails to adequately punish adequately for moral harms. Jonathan Baron and Ilana Ritov
have studied intuitions about penalties and compensation in tort law.
19
Though subjects were
highly sensitive to the moral distinctions, they ignored the information about deterrence
altogether, uniformly imposing punishments based on the moral rule that the punishment should
be proportionate to the outrageousness of the act, whether the punishment would be useful,
pointless, or even harmful.
20
In breach of contracts cases, people must make similar judgments.
Our hypothesis is that they will be highly sensitive to the moral dimensions of efficient breach,
ignoring the incentive effects of various possible policies. In the criminal context, John Darley
and Paul Robinson have repeatedly shown that subjects are more sensitive to morally salient
information than they are to factors associated with deterrence rationales, and that people punish
in line with retributive theories of justice.
21
This evidence suggested to us that people might also
be more averse to losses coming from someone who has promised to confer a benefit (e.g., a
promisor) than from someone with a neutral status (say, a negligent tortfeasor).
With the legal, moral, and economic arguments of normative theorists in mind, and in
19
Jonathan
Baron & Ilana Ritov. Intuitions about Penalties and Compensation in the Context of
Tort Law, 7 J. RISK & UNCERTAINTY 33 (1993).
20
Id.
21
Paul Robinson & John Darley, The Utility of Desert, 91 NW. U. L. REV. 453 (1997). Kevin
Carlsmith, John Darley & Paul Robinson, Why Do We Punish: Deterrence and Just Deserts as
Motives for Punishment, 83 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCH. 284 (2002).
9
light of evidence from psychology and behavioral economics, we undertook empirical research
to examine the nature of moral intuition and moral judgment in breach of contract cases.
II. EMPIRICAL STUDIES
Subjects in all studies were members of a panel recruited over a 10-year period, mostly
through their own efforts at searching for ways to earn money by completing questionnaires.
Approximately 90% of respondents were U.S. residents (with the rest mostly from Canada). The
panel is roughly representative of the adult U.S. population in terms of income, age, and
education
22
but not in terms of sex, because (for unknown reasons) women predominate in our
respondent pool.
For each study, we sent email to about 500 members of the panel, saying how much the
study paid and where to find it on the World Wide Web. Each study was a series of separate
web pages, programmed in JavaScript. The first page provided brief instructions. Each of the
others presented a case, until the last, which asked for (optional) comments and sometimes
contained additional questions. Each case had a space for optional comments. (We report some
comments in the discussion of the results to suggest possible conclusions and implications of the
quantitative results. Because they were optional, comments were not coded and analyzed
systematically.) Otherwise the subject had to answer all questions in order to proceed. The order
of cases was randomized (with one exception). The study was removed when about 75
responses had been submitted, with a target of 80. The studies are all available at
http://www.psych.upenn.edu/~baron/tess/. In a pilot study we asked subjects to read a series of
breach of contract scenarios and to answer questions about them. Subjects showed some
22
Linda Babcock, Michelle Gelfand, Deborah Small & Heidi Stayn. The Propensity to Initiate
Negotiations: Toward a Broader Understanding of Negotiation Behavior. Manuscript, Carnegie-
Mellon University (2003).
10
willingness to demand damages higher than expectation level as well as a preference for specific
performance as a remedy for breach.
B. Experiment 1: Loss Aversion and Motives for Breach
We predicted that subjects would be more sympathetic to a breacher who breaks a
contract in order to avoid a loss than an otherwise identical breacher who breaks a contract in
order to accept a more lucrative deal elsewhere. This is essentially a framing effect: in both
cases, the breacher will make more money by breaking the contract than by honoring it.
However, because people are more sensitive to the prospect of a loss than a foregone gain, we
hypothesized that they would find the notion of breaching in order to gain to be more offensive
than breaching to avoid a loss. We assume that subjects take the status quo to be the expected
benefit of the original contract, such that a lower profit for the promisor is seen as a loss. Thus,
we predicted that subjects would impose higher penalties in a breach to gain case than in a
breach to avoid loss case, and that they would find the former more morally objectionable than
the latter.
I. Method
In Experiment 1, 83 subjects participated, with 78% female. Ages ranged from 22 to 69,
with a median age of 42. In this study, we used a between-subjects manipulation, where half the
subjects read about a breach to avoid loss, and the other half read about a breach to gain. The
scenario described a contract for a kitchen renovation. In the Avoid Loss condition, subjects read
that "the contractor learns that the price of cabinets and countertop has skyrocketed, and the
contract price will barely cover the cost of materials. He decides to break his contract in order to
take other, more profitable work."
In the Gain condition, subjects read that "the contractor learns that there is a shortage of
11
skilled renovators in a nearby area, and he could charge much more there for a similar project.
He decides to break his contract in order to take other, more profitable work."
Subjects were asked to choose an appropriate amount of damages. We constructed an
eight-point scale based on the available numbers in the scenario. For these cases, subjects could
choose among the following 8 options: no compensation; a number between nothing and
expectation damages (e.g., “more than 0 but less than ...”); expectation damages; a number
between expectation damages and the difference between the buyer's reserve and the seller's
reserve; the difference between the buyer's reserve and the seller's reserve; more than the
difference between buyer's reserve and seller's reserve but less than the contract price; the
contract price; or a number greater than contract price. For the purposes of analysis, we used the
choices as points on a scale from one to eight.
23
Subjects were also asked to indicate to what extent the breacher should feel guilty should
he choose to pay the damages and break the contract.
II. Results
Subjects who saw the breach to gain scenario set the damages at a mean level of 4.08,
while subjects who saw the breach to avoid loss scenario set the level of damages at 3.14
(difference is significant, t=2.592, df=76.40, p=.0114), where 3 was expectation level. Subjects
did not assign significantly different levels of guilt on a three-point scale in the two conditions,
23
In this case, expectation damages were $3,000. Subjects chose from the following options:
1) No compensation
2) More than nothing but less than $3,000
3) $3,000
4) More than $3,000 but less than $9,000
5) $9,000
6) More than $9,000 but less than $20,000
7) $20,000
8) More than $20,000
12
though the small existing difference was in the hypothesized direction (more guilt in the breach
to gain scenario).
Using the same scenario, we saw the same main effect in a within-subjects design
24
, with
subjects assigning higher damages in the Gain condition than the Avoid Loss condition (mean
difference on 8-point scale=.341, t=2.303, df=87, p=.0237). We also found that subjects assigned
significantly more guilt in the Gain condition than in the Avoid Loss condition (mean difference
on a 3-point scale=.261, t=3.663, df=87, p=.0004).
C. Experiment 2: Timing
In this study, we wanted to know whether the time of the damages negotiation would
matter. We thought that once the breach is a fait accompli, the most salient fact in the scenario is
the broken promise. However, there are usually other opportunities to negotiate damages before
the breach has occurred. Therefore, we hypothesized that subjects would set lower damages if
they were negotiating the cost of a possible future breach rather than assigning blame once the
contract is irreparably broken.
We also wanted to collect initial data that would help us understand the origins of
subjects' punitive attitudes toward breach of contract cases. One possibility was that subjects
were not being prompted to think of the economic consequences of their judgments, that they
were not calculating the costs in a way that would allow them to see that expectation damages
would fully compensate the promisee. Another implication of the misunderstanding hypothesis is
that subjects would not see the economic incentives for expectation damages, both from the point
of view of general economic welfare and from the point of view of the promisee, who would be
24
Within-subjects data were collected as part of Experiment 2, where the gain/avoid loss
manipulation was simply tacked on to the beginning of the timing experiment so that we could
see within-subjects results of the framing manipulation.
13
unable to secure a contract at all under a system in which the penalties for breach were so
burdensome as to be a deterrent to contract at all. Another possibility is that subjects would
explicitly choose to impose an additional penalty, reasoning that the breach was a moral harm of
some kind and therefore should be discouraged. In Experiment 2, we asked subjects to indicate
the optimal level of damages overall, then from an economic point of view, and finally from a
moral point of view.
Because we were particularly interested in subjects' explicit attitudes, we used entirely
within-subjects tests for this study.
1. Methods
88 subjects participated in Experiment 2; 67% were female. Subjects ranged in age from
18 to 64, with a median age of 35.5.
This study includes a total of 5 screens, or 5 scenarios. The first two are identical to those
in Experiment 1: the kitchen renovation breach to gain, and the kitchen renovation breach to
avoid loss. The next three scenarios tested the timing hypothesis, and all involve the same
vignette describing a contract for a party rental. A couple, the Bakers, rents out a local restaurant
for their anniversary party, and the owner of the restaurant, Dave, is offered a much bigger fee
for the same night. We showed subjects three versions. In the first version, subjects read that the
couple "discuss with Dave what would happen if he breaks the contract. Then the Bakers set the
date and invite friends and family." In the second version, the owner approached the couple with
a request to negotiate an amount that would release him from the contract: "Dave calls to cancel
the Bakers' reservation...He informs Mrs. Baker that another party loved the space so much that
they offered $25,000 for the same night. Dave and Mrs. Baker discuss the situation and agree on
a fee that Dave will pay to release him from their contract." Finally, in the third version, the
14
breach is a foregone conclusion and the couple is not invited to negotiate the damages amount.
Subjects are told that an "impartial mediator to the situation must now decide whether and how
much Dave should compensate the Bakers." Each subject saw all three versions of the scenario.
We asked subjects to indicate the fee or penalty that they would set.
25
We also asked
subjects to indicate the optimal level of damages from two other perspectives. We asked them to
indicate the most efficient damages level: "If you wanted to set a policy that would yield the best
economic outcomes overall, what compensation level would you choose?" We also asked them
to indicate the level of damages most in line with "the best moral rule."
2. Results
Subjects assigned lower damages when the amount was negotiated rather than decided
after the breach. As we described above, we had three conditions: a liquidated-damages clause in
the contract; a request to be released from the contract; and a simple breach. The mean scale
values for compensation (where expectation damages are 3) were, respectively, 4.51, 4.53, and
4.88. The first two conditions did not differ, but the request and simple breach differed
significantly (t=2.079, df=87, p=.0405). In sum, subjects favored higher damages once the
promisor has definitively breached, but are slightly less punitive when they are asked to set a fee
for breach before the contract is irreparably broken.
Recall that in this study we also tested a within-subjects version of the framing study
25
In this case, expectation damages were $2,000. Subjects chose from the following options:
1) No compensation
2) More than nothing but less than $2,000
3) $2,000
4) More than $2,000 but less than $3,000
5) $3,000
6) More than $3,000 but less than $11,000
7) $11,000
8) More than $11,000
15
reported in Experiment 1.
Finally, we thought that subjects might indicate that the economically optimal level of
damages would be lower than the level that they set for the breacher. They did not. However,
they did indicate that the damages best reflected by the moral rule would be higher than the level
of damages they chose. Averaging across all the scenarios in Experiment 2, subjects set the
"moral damages" .422 points higher than their own damages assignment (t=5.302, df=87,
p<.001). This effect interacted significantly with the framing manipulation. The difference
between the moral penalty and the level of damages that subjects actually set was bigger in the
breach-to-gain case than in the avoid-loss case (t=2.341, df=87, p=.0216). The effect did not
interact significantly with the timing manipulation.
Experiment 3: Is a contract a promise?
In the first two experiments, our results suggested that people are often willing to impose
damages well above expectation level, and that they find breach morally objectionable (or at
least guilt-inducing) even when damages are paid. In this study, we want to ask what, exactly, is
the moral content of a contract. Our hypothesis is that subjects consider breaking a promise to be
a harm in itself, and that they will punish an intentional harm more severely than a negligent
harm.
In order to test this experimentally, we compared breaking a contract with causing an
identical loss negligently. Each of three scenarios was presented in two different versions. In one
version, subjects read a case of efficient breach, in which the promisor breaks the contract in
order to accept a more lucrative contract elsewhere. In the control condition, the same contract is
rendered impossible to complete when a third party negligently causes a harm that in turn
prevents performance. In this case, we are asking subjects not about the damages that would be
16
paid by the promisor, who is presumably excused from the contract, but rather the liability
damages paid by the third party. So, for example, either a contractor breaks the contract to take
another job, or a contractor is prevented from completing the contracted-for job because of a gas
leak negligently caused by a third party. In each condition, the financial harm is identical, and
the harm is confined to the harm of not being able to realize the benefit of the contract.
In this study, we made several important changes and additions. First, we asked subjects
to name the dollar amount of damages themselves, rather than asking them to choose among
levels of compensation as in the first two studies. Though this method introduces the problem of
anchoring effects and subject typing errors, it permits subjects to name an exact amount of
damages. Second, we directly asked subjects about the morality of the act of breaching the
contract rather than relying on the subjects' assignment of guilty feelings to the breacher (or on
the appropriate compensation from a moral point of view). Third, we asked subjects what the
promisor should do (breach or perform), and whether the law should force the promisor to honor
the contract.
1. Method
80 subjects answered a questionnaire on the World Wide Web. 76.3% of subjects were
female. Subjects ranged in age from 24 to 79, with a median age of 44. Subjects read six
scenarios and answered questions about each. In this study, there were three core scenarios
describing a contract. They describe contracts for backyard landscaping, floor refinishing, a party
rental, and a sale of used books. Below is one example:
Scenario:
The Millers are getting ready to sell their condo. Their real estate agent tells them that
their condo will be worth $10,000 more if they get the floors refinished (and you should
assume that the agent is correct). They meet with Todd, from Todd's Hardwood Floors,
agree on a price of $6,000 to refinish the floors, and they all sign the contract. Todd is
17
going to refinish the floors right before the condo goes on the market in early October.
Three of these scenarios were presented in one of two conditions, the promise condition and the
no-promise condition.
Promise Condition:
About three days before he is slated to work on the Millers floors, Todd gets an offer to
refinish all of the floors in another apartment building. If he accepts this offer, he will
make much more money, but he will not be able to refinish the Miller's floors. Todd
decides to take the new job and break his contract with the Millers.
No Promise Condition:
About three days before Todd is slated to start working on the Millers' floors, the owners
of the next apartment down, the Bakers, are trying to move a gas line in their own condo,
even though it is quite dangerous. They do not take proper precautions and the line
breaks, gas leaks, and the Millers' apartment is too toxic for Todd to do his work. The
Millers have already moved into their new home, so they are not personally affected by
the fumes. However, the fumes are quite toxic in the Millers' condo for more than a week,
so Todd is unable to refinish the floors before the condominium goes on the market.
(Note that Todd does not need to be compensated, because he gets a similar, highly
paying job for the same week once he is released from his contract with the Millers.)
In this study, we blocked the conditions. This means that half of the subjects first saw
each scenario in the promise condition, and then saw each scenario in the no promise condition;
the other half of the subjects saw the scenarios in the reverse order (first all no-promise, then all
promise). Within the blocks, the order of scenarios was random. We did this for two reasons. The
first is simply that we thought it would be less confusing for subjects. The second is that it
permitted us to do between-subjects analyses of their responses. By looking only at the first
block of responses for each subject, we can see their responses unaffected by their implicit
comparisons to the other condition.
2. Results
Our between-subjects tests of guilt and morality indicate that subjects thought that a
18
person who caused harm via breaking a contractual promise was more immoral and should feel
more guilt than a person who caused harm via negligence. On a 7-point scale where 7 is
extremely immoral and 1 is not immoral at all, the average rating of for a negligent wrongdoer
was 3.3, and the average rating for a breacher who caused an identical loss was 5.1 (test of the
difference is significant: t=5.281, df=74.58, p<.0001). Similarly, on a 7-point scale, subjects on
average felt that a negligent wrongdoer’s guilt should rate a 3.3, and a breacher’s guilt should
rate a 5 (Within-subject comparisons were also significant at p<.001. Test of the difference is
significant: t=4.686, df=76.01, p<.0001).
The responses to the question about damages were open-ended, and their distribution was
highly skewed. Taking the logarithm removed the skewness, but the distributions still had long
tails on both sides (i.e., an excess of extreme responses both high and low). Accordingly we
report trimmed means (10% on each side) based on the logarithms, but we use nonparametric
tests for inference. We report both t-tests and Wilcoxon tests for the tests of differences below.
Table 1 shows the means for each case in each condition, shown as a ratio of expectation
damages (Thus, if the promisee’s expectation was $1,000 and the average subject response was
$2,000, the ratio is 2. If the average subject response was $1,000, the ratio is 1. This was based
on the antilog of the mean log.)
Case 1: Refinish
Floors
Case 2: Landscape
Yard
Case 3: Cater Party
1.12
3.12
2.33
0.82
0.79
1.58
We analyzed the difference between the promise and no-promise condition in two ways.
First, we looked at our between-subjects measure, comparing the promise responses of the group
who saw the promise cases first to the no-promise responses of the group who saw the no-
promise responses first. Though the pattern of means and log ratios were consistent with our
19
hypothesis (higher damages in the promise condition), the test of differences was not statistically
significant (t=.4142, df=74.99, p=.6799. The Wilcoxon test also showed non-significance.). We
then looked at the within-subjects comparison. For this analysis, we took the mean of the
difference of each subject’s promise and no-promise damages responses. This was a highly
significant difference (t=4.318, df=79, p<.0001. Wilcoxon test, p=.001), meaning that when they
saw both kinds of case, subjects imposed much higher damages overall in the promise cases than
in the no-promise cases.
Finally, subjects were also inclined to report that the promisors should honor the contract
rather than pay damages and breach (even though it was clear in every case that the promisor
would be better off by breaching). Responses were fairly consistent across cases, with an average
of 75.8% of subjects responding that the promisor should honor the contract in a given case.
Subjects also indicated that they thought that the law should force the promisor, in many cases,
to honor the contract and perform. The average percentage of respondents who thought the law
should require specific performance was 66.7%.
II. DISCUSSION & IMPLICATIONS
A. Interpretation of Findings
Subjects distinguished between cases in which the promisor breaches in order to avoid a
loss of some kind and cases in which the promisor has been given a better offer; they imposed
higher damages on the latter and indicated that he should feel guiltier for his breach. These
contract scenarios seemed to tap into subjects’ moral intuitions about what it means to make and
break a promise. In typical usage, a promise is a promise to perform, not a promise to do
something as valuable as performance. Most non-contractual promises happen between people in
20
a non-market-based relationship.
26
In a personal relationship, it is inappropriate to offer money to
remedy a broken promise. Broken promises are harmful on two counts—the loss incurred by the
lack of performance, and the relational rift. This is not (or need not be) the situation, though,
with the homeowner and the flooring contractor or kitchen renovator. Their promises are only
commercial in nature, and the sole purpose of the contract is to provide each with a monetary
benefit. However, as long as subjects believe that breaking a contractual promise is a moral
violation, it is reasonable to think that breachers should not be permitted to profit (above the
expected benefit of the contract) from their intentional bad act. It may be for this reason that
subjects demanded higher damages when the incentive for breach was framed as a potential gain
rather than loss avoidance.
We also used a timing manipulation to compare subjects' responses to the question of what they
would demand, ex ante, to release the promisor from the contract, as opposed to how they would
apportion blame ex post. We predicted that subjects would give more moderate responses when
asked to consider a negotiated breach or a liquidated damages clause and more punitive when
asked to assign a penalty once the harm has been done. We thought that once faced with the fact
of the breach, the moral violation and the personal betrayal become very salient. Subjects were in
fact less punitive when asked to suggest an acceptable fee for releasing the contractor from his
obligation than when they were asked to levy damages after an irreparable breach.
Subjects’ responses in this study are in line with other findings about the effect of a sense
of betrayal on moral reasoning. In this study, we find that subjects imposed higher damages
when the cause of the lost benefit is the promisor than when the harm is caused by someone who
26
In psychological terms, we might think of the subjects as applying rules from the communal
sharing domain to the market pricing domain. See Alan Page Fiske, The Four Elementary Forms
of Sociality: Framework for a Unified Theory of Social Relations, 99 PSYCH. REV. 689 (1992).
21
has not made any promises. Sunstein suggests that people may see a betrayal of trust as an
independent harm. This is reasonable in the case of a personal promise. It is not clear, though,
that this reasoning is helpful for thinking through breach of contract cases in the legal context. If
expectation damages are to be fully enforced, the promisee's interests are protected. We can
argue that interpersonal trust is either not required (because external sanctions exist to enforce
the legal duties) or is not violated, because when the breacher pays damages he puts the promisee
in the position she would be in had the breach not occurred. It seems as though people reason
from a premise of trust, but in fact, the point of writing the contract out and making it legally
binding is to obviate the need for trust.
Finally, the most important implication of this study for law is that intuition treats a
contract like an obligation in tort. When a promisor breaches in order to make more money,
subjects want to treat him like an intentional tortfeasor, including levying punitive damages. In
Experiment 3, we explicitly contrasted two cases in which the promisee loses an expected
benefit. In the case of a negligence, subjects wanted the wrong-doer to pay an amount close to
the cost of the loss. However, when the wrong-doer intentionally breached the contract, subjects
consistently imposed higher damages, in some cases damages as high as two or three times the
cost of the loss.
These findings may also have implications for the ability of parties to make and break
contracts efficiently. People’s moral intuitions about contract law may make breach less frequent
than is economically efficient, and may inhibit the parties’ ability to settle out of court if there is
a breach. When parties disagree about appropriate damages in light of a breach of contract, they
may be less likely to settle out of court and more likely to undertake litigation. A possible
implication of our results is that parties will have different ideas about what constitutes a fair
22
resolution.
If parties think that a contract is a promise to perform, and not simply to confer a benefit
as valuable as performance, they may be less likely to breach at all. For individuals who are not
familiar with the rule of expectation damages (and we take this to be most laypeople), this would
be true because they believe that they are legally (and morally) obligated to perform. Researchers
have found that people believe that exculpatory clauses in contracts mean that they cannot seek
compensation.
27
A secondary finding in that line of research is that even though subjects
believed that exculpatory clauses could legally relieve a firm’s obligation to compensate its
consumers for harms it had caused, they did not think that contracts with exculpatory language
were less fair than contracts that left open the possibility of consumer compensation.
28
Our study
offers a kind of extension to these findings. In both cases, subjects thought that the parties were
morally bound by the specific language of the contract, even when contract law says that the
exculpatory clause is unenforceable or that the promisor can pay rather than perform.
More sophisticated parties may also be deterred from efficient breach because they do not
want to offend their customers or get a bad reputation. As we discussed above, empirical
research has demonstrated the real effects of psychological breach.
29
The loss of consumer trust
may have financial effects that override the potential profits from the breach, no matter that the
consumer’s judgment seems irrational. Parties to a contract will have different interactions with
one another and with the legal system depending on their beliefs about contracts. These beliefs,
in turn, may be partially informed by intuitions imported from the moral domain.
CONCLUSION
27
Stolle & Slain, supra note 24, at 91.
28
Id.
29
Robinson & Rousseau, supra note 23.
23
“The line between legal and moral guidelines is a very blurry one in my mind,
commented one subject. “I don’t think a judge can clearly exercise one without the other having
some bearing.” Our results suggest that the connection between law and morality is not a
philosophical abstraction; for most people, it is an entrenched component of their intuitions about
legal decision-making. People’s moral responses to the scenarios in our studies affected their
legal judgments. Subjects imposed higher damages for parties whom they judged to be more
morally culpable. Empirical results like those we have presented here have bearing on practical
legal matters, including bargaining during contract drafting as well as negotiations over the
breach of a contract. These results may also bear on moral theories of breach of contract, as we
identify some discontinuities and tensions between intuition and reason.