1
John Willinsky, The Intellectual Properties of Learning: A Prehistory from Saint Jerome to John
Locke (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2018).
OPEN ACCESS FINAL DRAFT
Chapter Twelve
An Act for the Encouragement of Learning
The final draftof this chapter has been made open access through a special
arrangement with the University of Chicago Press, reflecting their interest in
exploring the access themes raised in the book.
Note that the final draft, which has benefited from rounds of peer review and
revision before being accepted for publication by the press, differs at a great
many points from the published text of the book. The book benefited from
the pressexcellent copyediting, as well as my revisions and proofreading
(with the help of colleagues) in that process. Those who are unable to obtain
a copy of the published book from which to cite may wish to quote from and
reference the final draft of this chapter as follows:
John Willinsky, The Intellectual Properties of Learning: A Prehistory from Saint Jerome to John
Locke (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2018), open access final draft, chapter 12, available from
https://intellectualproperties.stanford.edu.
2
Chapter 12
An Act for the Encouragement of Learning
The two major philosophical statements of Locke’s career, the one touching on the
intellect and knowledge (Essay) and the other on property (Two Treatises), contain little
that bears directly on what we now think of as intellectual property. That may not be
surprising, given the concept did not yet have a name nor legislation to back it up when
Locke published these works in 1689. What is remarkable is that within a few years of
publishing these two books, Locke threw himself headlong into a legislative fray over the
regulation of printing that had a great deal to say about intellectual property (if still not
yet by that name), thanks to his efforts.
During the seventeenth century, the exclusive right to print a copy of a book in
Britain had been a topic of pressing interest to London’s StationersCompany, the king,
the Church of England, the Royal Society of London, and the fledgling university presses
at Oxford and Cambridge (as reviewed in Chapters 9 and 10). The property of a book that
was most at issue during this period was that it had been licensed by the crown and
registered with the Company of Stationers in what amounted to a perpetual monopoly.
This censorship-monopoly combination increasingly troubled scholars, such as Locke,
who were unable to obtain needed books at a fair price, if at all.
On January 2, 1693, Locke decided to do something about it. The story begins, as
much did in that time, with a letter. On that day, Locke wrote to his friend Edward
Clarke, then Whig member of Parliament from Taunton (and married to a relative of
Locke’s) on the state of the book trade. Parliament was considering the renewal, once
3
again, of the thirty-year-old Licensing of the Press Act of 1662. It had last been approved
in 1685, under James II, for seven years. In his letter, Locke asked Clarke to consider the
damage done by the StationersCompany monopolies granted by this Act:
I wish you would have some care of Book buyers as well as all of Book sellers,
and the Company of Stationers who haveing got a Patent for all or most of the
Ancient Latin Authors (by what right or pretence I know not) claime the text to be
their and soe will not suffer fairer and more correct Editions than any thing they
print here or with new Comments to be importedwhereby these most usefull
books are excessively dear to schollers.
1
The awarding of these patents could keep, he protests, a new edition of Aesop’s Fables
from being printed. The edition of Aesop he likely has in mind, he fails to mention, is the
English-Latin edition of the Fables that he had begun preparing some years before for
educational purposes, which faced just such patent hurdles.
2
Locke’s letter, however, was
too little too late. The Licensing of the Press Act was renewed in March of 1693.
3
It was
1
John Locke, “1586. Locke to Edward Clarke, 2 January 1693,” in Correspondence of John Locke, ed. E.
S. de Beer, vol. 4 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), 614-15.
2
Locke’s printer, Awnsham Churchill, requested the right from the StationersCompany to print what
became Locke’s AEsop’s Fables, in English & Latin, Interlineary, for the Benefit of Those Who Not Having
a Master, Would Learn Either of these Tongues (London: A. & J. Churchill, 1703), which was granted on
December 12, 1695, enabling him to print 1,000 copies without having to pay the Company for this
privilege, although the book was only published 8 years later; Donald F. McKenzie and Maureen Bell, A
Chronology and Calendar of Documents relating to the London Book Trade, 1641-1700 (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2005), 199, 207. On the other hand, Roger L’Estrange, who had earlier served Charles II
as Licensor of the Press, published a “registerededition of the fables in 1692 with Awnsham Churchill and
a number of other printers; Fables, of Aesop and other Eminent Mythologists: with Morals and Reflection
(London: R. Sare, A. & J. Churchill, et al., 1692).
3
In the House of Lords, eleven dissenting Peers issued a statement of protest against the Act, as it “subjects
all Learning and true Information to the arbitrary Will and Pleasure of a mercenary, and, perhaps ignorant,
Licenser, destroys the Properties of Authors in their Copies; and sets up many Monopolies”; A Complete
4
renewed this time, however, for only a two-year term, making it clear that the members
of Parliament had lost their enthusiasm for book licensing. Locke must have understood it
as such. He began to campaign in earnest against any further renewal of the Act. As part
of that effort, Locke worked with Edward Clarke, as well as John Freke, as its lawyer and
further Whig lobbyist and John Somers, who held the Parliamentary post of lord keeper
of the great seal and member of the privy council.
4
In his letters, Locke refers to this
group as his “Colledg(college).
The original passing of the Licensing of the Press Act in 1662 had been the latest
measure of English press regulation, dating back to actions taken by Henry VIII in the
1530s.
5
The Star Chamber required that books be licensed before being printed, while
restricting the number of master printers, as well as the importing of books from abroad.
6
During the Civil War, which saw the Star Chamber abolished, Parliament passed a similar
Licensing Order of 1643. Enter John Milton, otherwise a supporter of the
Parliamentariansstruggle against the Royalists. The poet Milton found his compatriot’s
Licensing Order objectionable in the extreme. In an unlicensed 1644 pamphlet entitled
Areopagitica, he offered a defense of the learning threatened by licensing. The pamphlet
Collection of the LordsProtests, from the First upon Record in the Reign of Henry the Third, to the Present
Time, vol. 1 (London, 1768), 163.
4
Locke was, during his period of exile (1683-89), part of a similarly informal group known as “Collegium
privatum medicumin Amsterdam; Locke also reports that Lady Masham “gives her service to the
Colledg”; “1845. Locke to John Freke and Edward Clarke, 8 February [1695],” Correspondence, vol. 5,
265.
5
Ronan Deazley, “Commentary on Henrician Proclamation 1538,” in Primary Sources on Copyright
(1450-1900), eds. L. Bently and M. Kretschmer, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, online.
6
Licensing can be traced back to Henry VIII’s November 16, 1538 proclamation requiring, in light of
“wronge teachynge and naughtye printed bokes,that books receive “his maiesties special licence”; cited
by Alfred W. Pollard, “The Regulation of the Book Trade in the Sixteenth Century,Library (1916) S3 7,
no. 25 (1916), 22-3. See Adrian Johnshelpful table ofMeasures Regulating the Press, 1586-1710"; The
Nature of the Book: Print and Knowledge in the Making (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998),
232. Johns cautions that “evasion, at least, was extensive; just as a large proportion of published books
were never entered [in the Stationer’s Register] so a large proportion lacked licenses”; ibid. 234. When
licensing “lapsed pamphlets and piracies seemed to flourish”; ibid.
5
was boldly identified as “A SPEECH of Mr. JOHN MILTON For the Liberty of
Unlicenc’d PRINTING, to the PARLAMENT OF ENGLAND.
7
It followed on the heels
of his much contested and anonymous tract in favor of divorce. The StationersCompany
cited this earlier tract as reason enough to have book regulation.
In Areopagitica, Milton argues that restrictions on press freedom “will be primely
to the discouragement of all learning and the stop of Truth.
8
It will be to the detriment of
“the purest efficacy and extraction of the living intellect [i.e., the author] that bredthe
books, in the first place.
9
He tied his fight to the interests of learning and writing, as such
licensing constitutes a “dishonor and derogation to the author, to the book, to the
privilege and dignity of learning.”
10
Milton asks, “how can a man teach with authority,
which is the life of teaching, how can he be a doctor in his own book… under the
correction of his patriarchal licenser?
11
If Milton’s pamphlet did little to bring about the
revoking of the Licensing Order, his impassioned, eloquent defense of press freedom,
learning, and the author’s intellectual property rights were likely influences on both
Locke (who had a copy of Miltons political works among his books), and Daniel Defoe
in the years leading up to the Statute of Anne 1710. In particular, Milton’s theme that
learning is something to be encouraged in any regulation of the press – given that book
licensing is “the greatest discouragement and affront, that can be offer'd to learning and to
7
John Milton, “Areopagitica,in Prose Writings, ed. K. M. Burton (London: Dent, 1958), 149.
8
Ibid.
9
Ibid., 149. Milton refers to “learningtwenty-eight times in the course of his essay, treating it as a source
of non-commercial property: “Truth and understanding are not such wares as to be monopolized and trade
in by tickets and statutes and standards. We must not think to make a staple commodity of all knowledge in
the land, to mark and license like our broadcloths and our woolpacks”; ibid., 168-69. Mark Rose argues that
Milton’s essay is “a key document in the emergence of the bourgeois public sphere,in which Milton
“portraying himself as a private man addressing the public at large through parliament, participates in the
discourse of the public sphere”; “The Public Sphere and the Emergence of Copyright: Areopagitica, the
StationersCompany, and the Statute of Anne,Tulsa Journal of Technology and Intellectual Property 12
(2009), 132.
10
Ibid., 167.
11
Ibid.
6
learned men– was a theme to be directly reflected in the 1710 statute.
12
Press regulation continued during the English Civil War (1642-51) and into the
Commonwealth and Protectorate under Cromwell that lasted until the Restoration in
1660. The growing political influence of newsbooks made them a favorite target among
the censors. The press faced further restrictive measures from Parliament in 1647 and
1649 (with Milton serving Cromwell at this point as Latin Secretary, placing him in the
very role of book licenser).
13
Then, with the Restoration of the crown, a chastened
Parliament instituted a new round of book licensing measures in 1662. This was in the
form of An Act for Preventing the Frequent Abuses in Printing Seditious Treasonable
and Unlicensed Books and Pamphlets and for Regulating of Printing and Printing
Presses.” The Press Act of 1662, as it was known, restricted printing to London, York,
and, in recognition of the universitieshistoric rights, Oxford and Cambridge.
14
The Act continued the close censorious and monopolistic association of crown,
church, and StationersCompany. It was regarded by the Whig opposition to Charles II as
a perfect example of Restoration excess. Parliament allowed the Act to lapse in 1679
amid the hostilities that Charles II was facing during the Exclusion Crisis from Lord
Shaftesbury and others. It was probably clear that the ensuing Whig-Tory pamphlet war
was unlikely to be contained by any licensing regime. The Licensing of the Press Act of
12
Milton, “Areopagitica,” 166. In 1667, the book licensor Rev. Thomas Tomkyns is said to have reluctantly
granted a license to Paradise Lost, given the light it accorded Satan; David Masson, “Introduction:
Biographical and Expository,in Poetical Works of John Milton, vol. 2, ed. David Masson (London:
Macmillan, 1890), 6.
13
Referring to Milton’s licensing of Mercurius Politicus, a weekly semi-official Commonwealth newsbook,
and on Milton’s continuing influence on debates over press regulation, at least up to 1707, see Ernest
Sirluck, “Areopagitica and a Forgotten Licensing Controversy,Review of English Studies 11, no. 43
(1960), 260-274.
14
Astbury reports that during the 1690s, the universities entered into an agreement with the Stationers
Company not to compete on the sales of English Stock-books, which included cheap editions of school-
books, psalm-books and almanacs, further reflecting the universitiesstruggle to find the right trade off of
privileges to make a go of scholarly publishing; The Renewal of the Licensing Act in 1693 and Its Lapse
in 1695,” The Library s5, 33, no. 4 (1978), 297, n2.
7
1662 was renewed again in 1685, when the not-to-be-excluded James II took the throne.
It also initially survived the Glorious Revolution of 1688 when James finally was
excluded from the throne, much as a similar act had survived the Civil War earlier in the
century. Yet, book licensing must have struck some as not entirely consistent with the Bill
of Rights of 1689, which limited the power of the monarchy. There was pressure,
particularly from the Whigs, to put an end to press regulation once and for all.
Locke’s Memo
The times were ripe by the 1690s for Locke’s “college” to weigh in on book licensing. In
1694, Edward Clarke was appointed to the Commons committee reviewing laws about to
expire, with the 1662 Licensing Act among them. To assist Clarke in preventing this Act
from being renewed yet again, Locke prepared a memorandum. He begins by sounding
the familiar trumpet, after Milton, in favor of a free press: I know not why a man should
not have liberty to print what ever he would speake.”
15
To have to obtain a license to
print a work in advance was like “gagging a man for fear he should talk heresy or
sedition.”
16
Yet it was not that anything goes. He allows that printer or author has to be
clearly identified in the book to ensure that someone will “be answerable for” any
transgressions of the law they have committed with the book.
17
But the risk of that
transgression is little enough for Locke, compared to the misuse that continues to follow
from the Licensing of the Press Act: “By this act England loses in general,as he puts it
15
John Locke, “Liberty of the Press (1694-5),” in Political Essays, ed. Mark Goldie (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1997), 331. Geoff Kemp notes that Spinoza, as well as Milton, precede Locke
in this fight; The End of Censorshipand the Politics of Toleration, from Locke to Sacheverell,
Parliamentary History 31 (2012), 52-3. Astbury observes that Locke’s critique resembles that of other
contemporary pamphlets in his collection on many points; “Renewal of the Licensing Act,” 307.
16
Ibid.
17
Ibid., 331.
8
at one point: “Scholars in particular are ground [down] and nobody gets [anything] but a
lazy ignorant Company of Stationers. To say no worse of them. But anything rather than
let mother church be disturbed in her opinion or impositions, by any bold voice from the
press.”
18
Locke then moves into what matters at least as much to him as press freedom.
This is the current “restraint of printing the classic authors.”
19
He sarcastically asks after
the value of such restraint: Does [it] any way prevent the printing of seditious and
treasonable pamphlets, which is the title and pretense of this act.
20
He is not objecting to
the prosecution of sedition, though he might well have, having been a candidate for such
prosecution when he fled to Holland in 1683. Rather, what bothers him is how badly
learning is served by the Stationers’ Company: “Scholars cannot but at excessive rates
have the fair and correct editions of these books and the comments [commentaries] on
them printed beyond [the] seas”; they are left with “scandalously illprinted” local
editions, given the lack of competition.
21
To bring the point home, Locke refers to an
imported edition of “Tully’s Works(Marcus Tullius Cicero) which he found to be “a
very fine edition, with new corrections made by Gronovius, who takes the pains to
compare that which was thought the best edition”; the work was “seized and kept a good
while in [the Company’s] custody,before it was sold with the booksellers “demanding
6s. 8d. per book.”
22
The problem is the overly broad and exclusive patents issued to the
Stationers’ Company without end or limit on Cicero’s works.
Locke’s overarching concern with scholars’ access rights leads him, finally, to a
18
Ibid., 335.
19
Ibid., 334.
20
Ibid.
21
Ibid., 332.
22
Ibid., 332-333.
9
backhanded commendation of at least one of the Act’s clauses. The Act requires that a
copy of every book printed be sent to, as he puts it, “the public libraries of both
universities.” This was what, you may recall, Thomas Bodley managed to secure from the
Stationers’ Company for the university library at Oxford. Locke complains that the
sending of books to the libraries “will be found to be mightily if not wholly neglected” by
the Stationers’ Company, however keenly it otherwise supported the Act.
23
The public
libraries book deposit policy at Oxford and Cambridge represents a recognition of
learning’s distinct economic and political position, which has long been sustained by
such compacts, with this book reviewing many instances of that position being renewed
and reformed.
In the face of the perpetual monopolies of the StationersCompany, Locke calls
for term limits on intellectual property rights, much as he qualified property rights in the
Second Treatise with his sufficiency and spoilage provisos. “Those [printers and
booksellers] who purchase copies from authors that live now and write,he states in his
Licensing Act memo, “it may be reasonable to limit their property to a certain number of
years after the death of the author or the first printing of the book as suppose 50 or 70
years.”
24
This would allow for new editions of older works, compared to current
difficulties, he pointed out, when “the Company of Stationers have a monopoly of all the
classic authors.”
25
Locke also objected to restrictions on importing books. This opposition aligns
23
Ibid., 336.
24
Locke, “Liberty of the Press,” 337. Joseph Lowenstein judges that Locke’s “opposition to perpetual
copyright is one of the most consequential aspects of Locke’s critique of the licensing bill,while pointing
out that it was inspired by the “limited-term privilegeof the old institution of the patent”; The Author’s
Due: Printing and the Prehistory of Copyright (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002), 230. In 1998,
the U.S. Copyright Act extended the length of copyright from 50 to 70 years after the author’s death.
25
Locke, “Liberty of the Press,” 332.
10
with his spoilage proviso with regard to property rights. To keep foreign books out of
English hands effectively wasted some portion of the potential learning these books
represented. His friend, Edward Clarke, takes up this theme of waste in his report to the
House of Lords by suggesting that the delays for book importers caused by the Act meant
that, as he vividly put it, “part of his Stock lie dead; or the Books, if wet, may rot and
perish.
26
When Locke bemoans in his memo that the Act is “so manifest an invasion on the
trade, liberty, and property of the subject,I take it that what is under siege are the
intellectual property rights of the learned and learning.
27
As Locke sees it, access to this
literature must be facilitated, rather than impeded by such unfair trade practices as
perpetual monopolies and book blockades: That any person or company should have
patents for the sole printing of ancient authors,he writes in the memo, “is very
unreasonable and injurious to learning.”
28
This is, of course, Milton’s theme, in objecting
to a licensing of the press that inevitably discourages learning.
Locke’s Further Reflections on the Press
Not long after Locke’s memo, in 1695, Clarke began to work with his fellow legislator,
Robert Harley, on a “Bill for the better Regulating of Printing and Printing Presses.
Their proposed bill had the virtue of exempting from state licensing those books dealing
with heraldry, science, and the arts. It offered no protection of StationersCompany
26
“Commons Reasons for disagreeing to the Clause for reviving the Printing Act,Journal of the House of
Lords 15 (18 April 1695), 546.
27
Ibid. 336.
28
Ibid., 337. Locke continues: “Tis very absurd and ridiculous that anyone now living should pretend to
have a property in or a power to dispose of the property of any copies or writings of authors who lived
before printing was known and used in Europe”; ibid.
11
monopolies or the universitiesprinting privileges.
29
Locke was not involved in the
drafting of Clarke and Harley’s first go at the new bill, but he jumped in soon enough by
proposing amendments to it.
30
Although a number of Locke’s suggestions have since
been lost, what is clear is that he was now prepared to make far more of the author’s
intellectual property rights than he had in his earlier memo. He proposed to Clarke that
the new bill “secure the author’s property in his copyfor a limited time.
31
He tied this
securing of the author’s property in the work to a registration process that, in the first
instance, protected the rights of learning. The printed book was initially to be deposited
for the use of the publique librarys of the said Universities.After this deposit, the bill
“shall vest a privileg in the Author… for __ years from the first edition.”
32
The exact
number of years he left up to Parliament to set, although he had earlier advocated 50 to
70 years after the death of the author.
Consider how Locke frames his case. Books are for the use of others through, for
example, the public libraries of the universities, while authors are vested with a limited
privilege in their books. There is no sense of outright or absolute ownership. He is
treating intellectual property as something one has an interest in or some claim on, much
as in the Two Treatises he writes of the “great difficulty, how one should ever come to
have a Property in any thing.”
33
In the case of books, the author has a property in a book
29
Cited by Astbury, “Renewal of the Licensing Act,” 321. Among those calling for a renewal of the
Licensing Act was John Wallis, Professor of Geometry at Oxford, and book licenser, who warned that the
university’s loss of privileges in printing profitable books would leave it unable to subsidize costly
scholarly works (a refrain still heard from university presses today); Astbury, “Renewal of the Licensing
Act,” 322.
30
Ibid., 312.
31
Locke, “Appendix, Documents relating to the termination of the Licensing Act, 1695,” Correspondence,
vol. 5, 795.
32
Ibid., 796.
33
John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1988), 2.27.
12
that earns the author, as an incentive, a limited-term privilege in the book (as well as a
longer-term accreditation for having written it, which is not part of the proposed
legislation). He also proposes that authors have a further right to control any subsequent
editions of their work. The author could exercise these rights were “within [blank] years
after its first edition be reprinted with or without the name of the author to it without
authority given in writing by the author or somebody entitled by him.
34
When he wrote
this, he was likely engaged in revising the third editions of both the Essay Concerning
Human Understanding and the Two Treatises.
35
In giving authors control of subsequent
editions, he is recognizing the authors interests and responsibilities in correcting and
improving their work with each new edition.
The StationersCompany lobbied vigorously against Clarke and Harleys Better
Regulating of Printing” bill and it stalled and died on the floor of the Commons in 1695.
The Company, which sought a straightforward renewal of the Licensing Act of 1662,
protested that the reforms proposed by Clarke and Harley were “wanting as to the
Security of [our] Property,which was a fair enough estimation of their intent.
36
Clarke
retaliated by circulating objections to the Company’s unfair and illogical trade practices,
drawing on the loss to learning that was in Locke’s memo. Yet even with their bill failing,
34
Locke, “Liberty of the Press,” 338. The “[blank]is Locke’s. An earlier anonymous pamphlet
complained of how, despite how “the Property of English Authors hath been always owned as Sacred
among the Traders,those who wrote commentaries on books “have been compelled to pay [licensors] their
extravagant Demands, for using the Bible Text to Comment upon”; as well, “many learned Authors have
been defrauded of their Rights thereby, who, after many years Pain and Study, and afterwards by a bare
Delivery of their Books to be Licensed or Transcribed, have been barred by surreptitious Entries made in
the said Register”; Reasons Humbly Offered To Be Considered Before the Act of Printing Be Renewed
(1692), 3.
35
The Essays “Epistle to the Readercontains Locke’s reflections on revisions made across five editions
(1689-1706) up to the final year, with provisions in his will for the final edition; a remarkably detailed
publishing history of Locke’s works is available in Jean S. Yolton, John Locke: A Descriptive Bibliography
(Bristol: Thoemmes, 1998).
36
Cited by Raymond Astbury, The Renewal of the Licensing Act in 1693 and Its Lapse in 1695,” The
Library s5, 33, no. 4 (1978), 312.
13
the House of Commons and the House of Lords still went ahead and voted that year not
to renew the Licensing of the Press Act of 1662. The Act expired on May 3, 1695, putting
an end to well over a century of oppressive and easily corrupted press regulation. The
great nineteenth-century historian and politician, Thomas Babington Macaulay, declared
the Act’s expiry a historic moment: “English literature was emancipated, and
emancipated for ever, from the control of the government.
37
Closer to the ground, Sir
William Trumbull wrote in a letter at the time, of how “since the Act for Printing Expired
London swarmes with seditious Pamphletts.”
38
Locke’s part in the defeat of the Licensing Act was enough to make one
biographer, Maurice Cranston, political science professor at the London School of
Economics, praise his subject’s political realism, for “unlike Milton, who called for
liberty in the name of liberty, Locke was content to ask for liberty in the name of trade,
and unlike Milton, he achieved his end.
39
It does suggest that philosophers might join
with poets as “the unacknowledged legislators of the world,as Shelley proposed in his
defense of poetry.
40
What mattered to Locke “in the name of trade” was the trade in
learning, and it came up briefly that same year of 1695 with the publication of what
proved to be Locke’s last substantial publication, The Reasonableness of Christianity as
Delivered in Scriptures.
In this book, Locke sets out the various ways in which reason serves revelation (as
he does at points in the Two Treatises). In this late work, he seeks to correct another
37
Thomas Babington Macaulay, The History of England, from the Accession of James II, vol. 4
(Philadelphia: Butler, 1856), 377.
38
Cited by Astbury, “Renewal of the Licensing Act," 317.
39
Maurice Cranston, John Locke: A Biography (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1957), 387. Astbury:
“Clearly, the Commons' objections owed much to Locke's Memorandum of 1694, even though his
expressions of animosity towards Court and Church as the leading champions of preprinting censorship
were expunged”;The Renewal of the Licensing Act,” 315.
40
Percy Shelley, A Defense of Poetry, ed. Mary Shelley (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1904), 90.
14
common misconception about knowledge, and in particular the knowledge of such vital
matters as morality and ethics. Such knowledge has for too long, he notes, been treated as
a “private Possessionalone, when it is always already something more than that:
Thus the whole stock of Human Knowledge is claimed by every one, as his
private Possession, as soon as he (profiting by others Discoveries) has got it into
his own mind; And so it is: But not properly by his own single Industry, nor of his
own Acquisition. He studies, ‘tis true, and takes pains to make a progress in what
others have delivered; But their pains were of another sort, who first brought
those Truths to light, which he afterwards derives from them. He that Travels the
Roads now, applauds his own strength and legs that have carried him so far in
such a scantling of time. And ascribes all to his own Vigor, little considering how
much he owes to their pains, who cleared the Woods, drained the Bogs, built the
Bridges, and made the Ways passable; without which he might have toiled much
with little progress.
41
There may be little original in Locke pointing out that we stand on the shoulders
of giants or at least owe a debt to those who came before us. However, this is also a
comment on the common nature of the “whole stock of Human Knowledge.” It is the
very business of learning to make the intricate, collective origins of knowledge part of the
public record, which scholars help to do by crediting those who first brought those
41
John Locke, “The Reasonableness of Christianity as Delivered in Scriptures,in Writings on Religion,
ed. Victor Nuovo (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 199-200. With thanks to Joanna Picciotto, who
“made the Ways passablefor me by pointing out this passage in Locke; Labors of Innocence in Early
Modern England (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2010), 265.
15
Truths to light,” as he puts it here. As learning has grown since his day, so have the
credit-conscious demands of referencing those to whom we are indebted. The intellectual
properties of learning are about enabling scholarsto make a progress in what others
have delivered,” just as this history of ideas keeps them from claiming any of it as a
“private Possession.”
At his death in 1704, Locke provided in his will for the distribution of a number of
his titles to “the publick Library of the University of Oxford,as if to recognize the
public claim on these works, with part of that claim an identification of his authorship. In
the will, he refers to how the Reverend Dr. Hudson, Library Keeper of the Bodleian
Library, had written to him “desireing of me for the said Library the books whereof I was
the Author.
42
Locke explains in the will that he had sent those works “publishd under my
name,only to receive back a note indicating that these books “were not understood fully
to answer the request.”
43
With this last will and testament, Locke states that “I do hereby
further give to the publick Library of the University of Oxford these following
books…[including] two Treatises of Government whereof Mr. Churchill has published
severall editions but all very uncorrect.”
44
As such, he settled his debt to learning’s claims
(always, the corrections) and property rights. Although he did not live to see the passing
of the Statute of Anne of 1710, it was to reflect a good part of his advocacy for learning.
Piracy’s Interlude
Immediately following on the expiry of print licensing in 1695, the streets of London
were awash in the hawking of newspapers, cheap pirated editions of books and
42
Locke, “Will,Correspondence, vol. 8, 425.
43
Ibid.
44
Ibid., 426.
16
magazines, scandalous and obscene pamphlets from upstart printers and booksellers. As
Locke had held, the existing libel and blasphemy laws were brought to bear against these
print criminals who faced search warrants and arrests, as well as new laws such as the
1698 Act for the More Effectual Suppressing of Blasphemy and Prophaneness.
45
The
StationersCompany denounced, with increasing rancor and outrage, a market flooded
with cheap reprints of its titles. Its members cast such acts as piracy. The term started to
be used in the 1680s for those who “stoletitles assigned to others in their Register.
46
It
was, in fact, a free market for almost the first time in print materials. The monopolies
were gone that the Stationers' Company’s well-established printers and booksellers had
enjoyed over the past century and more. The so-called pirates were not above citing lofty
principles, to borrow a vivid instance from London bookseller Benjamin Motte, a couple
of decades later: “The World has an absolute and indisputable power over all that appear
in print.Motte was defending his printing of an abridged edition of the Philosophical
Transactions in 1722 (although he was as ready to sue when his copyright on Jonathan
Swift was infringed by a Dublin printer).
47
The StationersCompany was having none of the world-has-a-right bunk. It turned
to Parliament for remedy. But reintroducing regulation was an uphill battle. In the years
following the Licensing Act’s expiry, the Company promoted one unsuccessful
45
Kemp, “The End of Censorship,’” 55. This Act in 1698 made it a crime to deny the Holy Trinity in
speaking, writing, or teaching, which Locke had done, in effect, a few years earlier by not mentioning it in
The Reasonableness of Christianity. Locke was not prosecuted nor the book suppressed, although he
engaged in an exchange of published letters with Bishop Stillingfleet, who attacked his Essay as a threat to
the faith, beginning in 1696.
46
Adrian Johns, Piracy: The Intellectual Property Wars from Gutenberg to Gates, (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2009), 41. On the origins of the term, John Fell refers, in a 1674 letter, to the Stationers
Company as “land-pirats,for treading on the university’s “propertie in Printing”; cited by Johns, Nature of
the Book, 344. The Oxford English Dictionary credits J. MennesRecreation for Ingenious Head-peeces in
1654 with first use of piracy in this sense.
47
Cited by ibid., 353.
17
Parliamentary bill after another. In 1704, the year of Locke’s death, a Bill to Restrain the
Licentiousness of the Press was introduced into Parliament. As the force behind the Bill,
the Stationer’s Company hid its economic interests behind the shield of the community’s
moral safety. The members of the House of Commons readily saw through it and were
not inclined to return to Company monopolies. Across Europe, and especially in that
haven for learning that was Holland, unlicensed printing and reprinting appeared to have
a certain intellectual excitement going for it, amid the blustering, nose-thumbing piracy.
48
There were some prepared to speak out in support of authorsrights in book
publishing, which had not played a part in the seventeenth-century licensed press. Among
them was Daniel Defoe. This was well before he found his legs as a novelist, when he
was still a pamphleteer and journalist. In 1703, Defoe published an anonymous defense
of press liberty, Essay on the Regulation of the Press, which began: “All Men pretend the
Licentiousness of the Press to be a publick Grievance, but it is much easier to say it is so,
than to prove, or prescribe a proper Remedy.”
49
Defoe had already, a year earlier in 1703,
proven Locke’s point about the sufficiency of post-publication prosecution. Defoe was
charged with libel, after releasing an anonymous satirical pamphlet taking on the Church
of England’s regard for Dissenters. He was sentenced to be publicly pilloried on three
occasions. He was not one to let an opportunity go to waste. He composed a Hymn to the
Pillory“HAIL! Hi'roglyphick State Machin– which he had distributed during his time
in the stocks, while arranging for his hymn to be sold nearby. Flowers were thrown at his
48
Among the reprint examples that Johns introduces is that of Locke’s works in “Dublin, Glasgow,
Amsterdam, The Hague, Rotterdam, Geneva, Brussels, Paris, Leipzig, Uppsala, Jena, Mannheim, Milan,
Naples, Stockholm (by order of the Swedish Riksdag, no less), and, ultimately, Boston”; ibid., 50. Johns
refers to “chain reactions of reappropriation, generally unauthorized, and often denounced,” before
concluding that “no piracy, we might say, no Enlightenment”; ibid.
49
Daniel Defoe, An Essay on the Regulation of the Press (London, 1704), 3.
18
feet, rather than rotten fruit and eggs.
50
Still, he ended up doing prison time for libel.
51
In his Essay on the Regulation of the Press, Defoe follows Milton and Locke in
pressing the point that the “License of the Presswas not likely to be consistent with “the
Encouragement due to Learning” or “the Liberty of this Nation.”
52
The encouragement of
learning comes up more than once in Defoe’s tract as the very thing about the press that
needs to be protected. Defoe bemoaned how the “pirating Books in smaller Print, and
meaner Paperwas, among other things and concurring with Milton, “a Discouragement
to Learning.”
53
As it goes with the freedom of ideas, this encouragement of learning theme was
picked up by the printers and booksellers as a promising line of attack on an unregulated
press and print piracy. The StationersCompany was likely behind three anonymous
petitions to Parliament, beginning with the 1706 one-page Reasons Humbly Offer'd for a
Bill for the Encouragement of Learning, and the Improvement of Printing.
54
This petition
opens with a concern for the “Many Learned Men [who] have been at great Pains and
Expence in Composing and Writing of Books.” It takes a Lockean stance on the author’s
“undoubted Right to the Copy of his own Book, as being a Product of his own Labor.It
reflects the Miltonic worry that Learned Men will be wholly Discouraged from
50
Paula R. Backscheider, Daniel Defoe: His Life (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 1989), 118. Daniel Defoe,
Hymn to the Pillory: An Online Edition, ed. Jess McCarthy (2013).
51
Defoe was not alone in facing charges, as John Feather lists 36 works prosecuted, for blasphemy, breach
of Parliamentary privilege, and like offences, between the end of licensing in 1695 and the Statute of Anne,
1710; “The Book Trade in Politics: The Making of the Copyright Act of 1710,” Publishing History, 8
(1980), 26.
52
Ibid., 15. Defoe continued to protest, in his Review, the lack of an author’s right in his copy, disrupted by
“Piracies, and Invasions of Property”; cited by Ronan Deazley, “Commentary on Defoe's Essay on the
Regulation of the Press (1704)” in Primary Sources on Copyright (1450-1900), eds. L. Bently and M.
Kretschmer, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, online.
53
Regulation of the Press, 27.
54
“Reasons Humbly Offer'd for a Bill for the Encouragement of Learning, and Improvement of Printing
(London, 1706), Primary Sources on Copyright (1450-1900), eds. L. Bently and M. Kretschmer, University
of Cambridge, Cambridge, online.
19
Propagating the most useful Parts of Knowledge.” It introduces, in closing, the requisite
image of a bereft widow-of-the-author, in this case “of the late Arch-Bishop Tillotson,
who was generously provided for by “Booksellers,” although this support was threatened
by print piracy.
In 1709, a further petition to Parliament presented “REASONS Humbly Offer’d,”
yet again, for a “BILL for the Encouragement of Learning.
55
This time the title
additionally called for "the Securing of Property of Copies of Books to the Rightful
Owners thereof. Learning became the focus of this battle over print regulation to a
degree that far exceeded its slight and tenuous market share in the book trade.
56
The
StationersCompany’s piracy complaints were being exacerbated by a flood of recent
reprints from Scottish printers taking advantage of the 1707 Act of Union to forge a Great
Britain of enterprising booksellers.
57
The 1709 petition was one of the last of perhaps a
dozen attempts on the part of the StationersCompany, the Church of England, and even
the University of Oxford to reinstate the Licensing Act or something very much like it.
58
In 1710, this brief interlude of unregulated printing came to an end in Great Britain.
The Statute of Anne 1710
If print piracy drove this legislation, the Statute of Anne still amounts to more than a legal
55
“Reasons Humbly Offer'd for a Bill for the Encouragement of Learning, and for the Securing of Property
of Copies of Books to the Rightful Owners thereof” (London, 1709), Primary Sources on Copyright (1450-
1900), eds. L. Bently and M. Kretschmer, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, online.
56
John Feather, A History of British Publishing (London: Routledge, 1988), 57-60.
57
Johns: “The invention of copyright was largely a response to a piracy feud overflowing with national
resentments, namely the attempt of Scottish reprinters to compete with London’s book trade”; Piracy, 13.
58
8 Anne, c.19. See The Statute of Anne, April 10, 1710, Avalon Project, Lillian Goldman Law Library,
Yale University, 2008, online. Feather lists eleven unsuccessful bills relating to the book trade brought
before Parliament between 1695 and 1710; “Book Trade in Politics,” 22. Johns calculates that the
StationersCompany called on Parliament fifteen times for some form of legislative protection; Nature of
the Book, 353.
20
remedy for a highly disrupted and vibrant marketplace. It was not a return to the
seventeenth-century compact among crown, church, and guild. In this new legislation
Parliament combined the author’s natural rights in a text with the public good of learning.
In an initial draft, the Statute of Anne refers toBooks and Writingsas the undoubted
Property of authors, as such property was (in a Lockean phrase) “the Product of their
Learning and Labor.”
59
In the final version, the earning of this right is left implicit. The
author’s property claim to a text is not being legislated; that is left to natural and common
law. On the other hand, learning’s role in motivating this legislation is made explicit in
the statute’s subtitle which begins An Act for the Encouragement of Learning.
The Statute opens with the StationersCompany’s complaint that “printers,
booksellers, and other persons have of late frequently taken the liberty of printing…
books and other writings, without the consent of the authors or proprietors of such books
and writings, which leads “too often to the ruin of them and their families.”
60
Authors
are portrayed as the natural owners of their compositions. They have a right to profit from
this labor, as “learned menwho strive to “compose and write useful books.”
61
Thus, the
author (or assignee) “shall have the sole liberty of printing and reprinting such book and
books for the term of fourteen years.”
62
The author may be credited forever for having
written the book – again, this natural right was not being legislated – but the exclusive
59
Cited by R. Deazley, Commentary on the Statute of Anne 1710,” in Primary Sources on Copyright
(1450-1900), eds. L. Bently and M. Kretschmer, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, online. As well,
Milton and Defoe used the phrase “Discouragement to Learningwhich was in the original draft of the
Statute; ibid.
60
Feather establishes the degree to which the StationersCompany influenced the final wording of the
Statute – it did bear expenses associated with seeing the Statute through – with the exception of a term-
limit on copyright; “Book Trade in Politics,” 36.
61
This language dates back to the Company’s 1706 petition, which begins, “Whereas many Learned Men
have been at great Pains and Expense…”; “Reasons Humbly Offer'd for a Bill for the Encouragement of
Learning, London (1706),” in Primary Sources. While any author was to a degree learned, in early
eighteenth-century Britain, the Company had in this earlier petition referred to “a Gentleman [who] has
spent the greatest Part of his Time and Fortune in a Liberal Education”; ibid.
62
8 Anne, c.19.
21
right to make copies of the work was restricted to an initial fourteen years, with the
prospect of renewing it for another fourteen years (while works registered prior to the
Statute are granted a continuing exclusive right to copy for twenty-one years). The
Statute requires that books “before such publication, be entered in the register book of the
Company of Stationers, in such manner as hath been usual.” This use of term limits with
monopoly rights had been used with patents granted for inventions for some time. In both
cases, such rights were regarded as an “encouragementor incentive, intended to ward
off “ruin” while author and inventor prepared further masterpieces.
These limits also reflect the troubled politics of monopolies in this emerging
liberal democracy. Allow me a slight digression on this theme, going back to the Statute
of Monopolies of 1624. This Statute was an early Parliamentary victory against King
Charles I in curbing the widely abused royal prerogative of granting trade monopolies to
favored subjects of the realm. The Statute dared to declare that such privileges bore the
“untrue pretences of publique good” and were nothing less than “mischievous to the State
by raising prices of commodities.”
63
The 1624 Statute pronounced these monopolies null
and void. Only legitimate inventions “anie manner of New manufacture” – warranted a
patent and for a restricted period of fourteen years (or twenty-one if prior to the Statute).
This is the term-limit model followed by the Statute of Anne covering the author’s
exclusive right to copy.
The 1624 Statute did not actually put an end to the crown’s habit of granting
monopoly privileges. Charles I’s continued use and abuse of the monopoly patents was
63
The complaint in the Statute was that the patents were granted uppon misinformacions and untrue
pretences of publique good many such grauntes have bene unduly obteyned and unlawfully putt in
execucion to the great grievance and inconvenyence of your Majesties subjects”; “Statute of Monopolies,
Westminster (1624),” in Primary Sources on Copyright (1450-1900), eds. L. Bently and M. Kretschmer,
University of Cambridge, Cambridge, online.
22
among the factors contributing to the English Civil War. In revoking and limiting patents,
the 1624 Statute made an exception of print (as well as gunpowder), allowing perpetual
monopolies to continue for reasons that we might identify today as national security.
Thus, Charles II had no problem with the Press Act of 1662. The Statute of Anne
represented a break with that past. It was a further Parliamentary assertion of elected
authority against the remnants of royal prerogative, with Parliament’s endorsement of
learning in the emerging spirit of the Enlightenment bringing this point home.
The Statute directs four of its roughly ten provisions toward the encouragement of
learning. It grants learning distinct property rights (with two of the measures continuing
rights that had been granted in the Licensing Act of 1662). Among the new rights, the
Statute first of all offers a remarkably direct remedy to Locke’s concerns over the price of
learned books: “The Vice-Chancellors of the Two Universities… the Rector of the
College of Edinburgh... have hereby full Power and Authority… to Limit and Settle the
Price of every such Printed Book… as to them shall seem Just and Reasonable.”
64
Now,
to be fair, this right is also extended to the archbishop and lord chief justice, and thus
applies outside of the university.
Other privileges are granted to the universities on behalf of learning. The Statute
continues the requirement of the earlier Act that printers and booksellers provide a copy
of each new book printed to university and state libraries, as if to acknowledge the value
of a well-stocked intellectual commons set apart from the book-selling market: “Copies
of each Book… upon the best Paper… be Delivered… for the Use of the Libraries of the
Universities of Oxford and Cambridge, the Libraries of the Four Universities
in Scotland, the Library of Sion College in London, and the Library commonly called the
64
8 Anne, c.19.
23
Library belonging to the Faculty of Advocates at Edinburgh.”
65
If the book-price-setting
powers of vice-chancellors have withered away and disappeared, the legal deposit of
published works in libraries has become a common legislative requirement throughout
the world.
66
The Statute also disallowed any restrictions on importing “any books in Greek,
Latin, or any other foreign language printed beyond the seas,” as if to address another of
Locke’s concerns with the earlier Act.
67
And finally, in a fourth measure, the Statute
declares that nothing herein is to “prejudice or confirm any right that the said
universitieshad “to the printing or reprinting any book or copy already printed, or
hereafter to be printed.”
68
The Statute certainly refers, more generally and more often, to “the author of any
bookand “any such book” rather than focusing exclusively on learned men. It ensures
the rights of the “proprietors of such books and writings,which are the booksellers and
printers to whom authors commonly sold the rights to their work. Yet along with authors
and proprietors, learning is very much present in Britain’s initiation of the age of
copyright in 1710, when Parliament passed legislation “vesting the copies of printed
books in the authors or purchasers of such copies, during the times therein mentioned.”
69
65
Ibid.
66
Richard Bell, “Legal Deposit in Britain (Part 1),” Law Librarian 8, no. 1 (1977), 5.
67
8 Anne, c.19.
68
Ibid. The universitiesprinting activities were called to account on occasion. John Twigg discusses how
during the Civil War, Parliament was given to regulating printing, with John Pym complaining in 1640 that
the presses “published and maintained in the Universitieswere spreading Royalist works, while
Cambridge’s licensing of Royalist books led to the arrest of a college master; Richard Holdsworth; The
University of Cambridge and the English Revolution, 1625-1688 (Cambridge: Boydell Press, 1990), 84-86.
69
8 Anne, c.19, 2. In 1486, the city of Venice issued a patent to Marcus Sabellicus for his Historiae rerum
venetarum ab urbe condita, which recognized his right in this property without creating a legal category of
ownership for authors, as the Statute does. See Pamela O. Long, who notes that such patents “rarely
prevented piracy” and were a “commercial privilege,” and not connected to “the originality of the author’s
expression”; Openness, Secrecy, and Authorship: Technical Arts and the Culture of Knowledge from
Antiquity to the Renaissance (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 2001), 11.
24
The Statute of Anne grants or affirms privileges for the learned that are perpetual and
without limit. The learned could expect books to be priced fairly through the powers of
the university’s vice-chancellor; they could import cheaper and better editions from
abroad; they could prepare such editions themselves and have them printed at the
university press; or they could simply go to the university library and find the works on
the shelves. These legislated privileges are acts of good faith, anticipating that increases
in learning will provide return enough to the society as a whole. This was how the store
of learning had been supported by the larger world in the past through the libraries of
abbey, convent, school, and university.
A similar appreciation for how learning forms a clear and worthy goal of
intellectual property law was to appear in the U.S. Constitution nearly eight decades later
in 1787. The Constitution gives Congress the power to promote the Progress of Science
and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive
Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
70
Both the Statute of Anne and this
constitutional clause have learning as their stated purpose, and subsequent United States
legislation was to provide exceptions and privileges for learning, as discussed in this
book’s first chapter.
71
In 1710, the British legislation bound authors, booksellers, and printers, as well as
the universities and their libraries, within a legal structure that forms the cornerstone of
today’s intellectual property regime (involving copyrights, patents, trademarks, and trade
70
U.S.C. 1, 8.
71
Oren Bracha: “When, in the late eighteenth century, Americans created their first copyright regime – first
through state enactments and then by the federal 1790 Copyright Act – they used the British Statute of
Anne as their doctrinal blueprint. Despite a few changes and omissions, the degree of similarity on the level
of basic concepts, structure, and text between the 1790 Copyright Act and the 1710 British statute is
remarkable”; “The Statute of Anne: An American Mythology,Houston Law Review 47 (2010-11), 877-78.
25
secrets). The Statute recognizes learning as the source of a valued class of properties.
This class of properties has been instrumental, I have tried to demonstrate, in the
historical formation and appreciation of intellectual property as a concept, even as this
class stands apart from other types of what are recognized as intellectual property. This
class consists of the properties by which learning is distinguished, properties that I have
identified in terms of access, accreditation, autonomy, communality, sponsorship, and
use. These properties take both material and intangible forms, operate as rights and
cultural practices, apply to texts and institutions, and change by period and place. In some
basic way, they have also persisted across this history in cloister, school, college, library,
and academy. The properties tend to distinguish learning from other human activities, not
least of all for how the properties produced by the human intellect in the case of learning
are intended to be used to develop others’ intellectual capacity. Allow me to briefly recap
the history of these six properties, in light of their continuing relevance.
Access: To begin with the right that initiated this book, this history has been full
of the provisions that people made to facilitate learned access, including Jerome’s
network of friends from Bethlehem to Rome; the Benedictine annual handing out of
books from the monastic library chest; the Islamic libraries with fellowships for travelling
scholars; and the stocking of the Bodleian Library in Early Modern Oxford by
benefactors and printers. This assumed right and responsibility of access is what
motivated the translation movements of Arabic texts into Latin during the twelfth and
thirteenth centuries and the humanist recovery of Latin and Greek manuscripts beginning
in the fourteenth. Nothing was more intellectually stimulating than prospects of access,
which inspired sharing and copying. Yet the learned excluded and occluded access at
26
historic points. Recall Margaret Cavendish’s appeal to the universities against banishing
women (not to mention other religions and cultures). Or, how Erasmus encountered a
sheer lack of trust and generosity among colleagues. Still, it was the ongoing institutional
efforts to improve, restore, and expand access that were encoded in the Statute of Anne
clauses bearing on library book deposit, unrestricted book importing, and reasonable
book pricing.
Accreditation: The work of the scholar is also marked by tendencies to credit (and
crab about) others’ work. A scholar’s handling of credits becomes an intellectual property
of the work produced, and an identity mark much as a silversmith’s hallmark. Jerome and
Augustine credit Cicero and Virgil to demonstrate antiquity’s value for Christian
arguments, while Cassiodorus built a model library to that end. Bede is clear about his
following in the footsteps of the church fathers, enabling him to break new ground in his
claims for learning. At the medieval universities, scholars readily acknowledge Avicenna
and Averroes for easing their way into Aristotle, natural history, and medicine. Crediting
is repayment for use in a credit economy based on reputation. One polishes another’s star
to shine brighter oneself, and a set of references form their own identifiable constellation
within that great firmament held in common.
Autonomy: Learning’s tendency to pull away from the flow of life has long been a
part of what it requires. In the Middle Ages, the abbey was self-governing (if class-
reproducing) in ways that popes enabled. Still, standing apart often proved a
vulnerability, as Abelard found with Bernard of Clairvaux, and as Aquinas could attest to,
given his part in the condemnation of the university. Unhappy kings could subject
monasteries to dissolution, only to have their endowment give rise to colleges with still
27
greater autonomy in their learning (if still susceptible to overzealous royal visits).
Universities gained autonomous printing rights in Britain, but stumbled for some time
before the brute economic force of London’s commercial monopolies. Negotiating this
necessary autonomy became an intellectual property of learned work, with this theme
often taken up in prefatory remarks, whether by Anselm, Hildegard, Locke or, in an
apologia, by Abelard.
Communality: Christian monasticism gave learning in the West its communal
beginnings, with book, table, and pen as things held in common by the Rule of Benedict.
The great libraries of Islam were open to travelling scholars, such as Avicenna, for which
they provided support. This communal spirit informs Erasmus’ tireless improvements to
the common stock of adages, which then circulated, cheaply and pirated, throughout the
print market. This bookish commons was a thing of humanist patrons’ private libraries
and the public libraries of the ancient universities. It operated as a great collective right of
access and use among the learned to be endlessly acted upon over the course of a
lifetime. It inspired much copying, translation, editing and, above all, commentary, which
further opened the intellectual properties of these shared works.
Sponsorship: Among these properties, sponsorship was undoubtedly the prime
mover of learning’s incorporation in the West. The abbeys, convents, priories, schools,
colleges, and academies, all of which provided a chartered home for learning, depended
on the kindness of strangers, family, nobility, and court. Benefactors founded and funded
these institutions, enabling them to stand apart from the world and that much closer to
heaven. While the course of this patronage was neither steady nor certain across the long
Middle Ages covered in this book, such beneficence continued to be renewed and found
28
afresh, with women of a certain standing often playing a key role. It was later cut with
commercial concerns among the universities, following the introduction of tuition and
then print, with all its privileges and monopolies, in the age of commerce. Among others,
Boethius, Averroes, Petrarch, and Locke provide lessons on the personal whims and
favors of patrons, against the steadier grip of learning’s institutional endowments.
Use: Learning’s final property in this set, as I have it, is the right of use. It was
known in Roman law as usufruct, and allowed for use that did not alter the property. It
has long held a special place within the commonwealth of learning. One scholar judges
(uses) another on their use of yet a third scholar’s work, with that third scholar as likely
Aristotle as anyone, after the Latin Translation Movement. On the other hand, the church
was prepared to pronounce Abelard’s interest in biblical contradictions a decided misuse
of Scripture, while Aquinas was condemned for over-use of Aristotelian reasoning in
theological matters. Hernández assumed that his ample use of Aztec medical practices
called for repayment through a Nahuatl translation of his findings. Oldenburg defended
his use of the Royal Societys papers as “necessary for promoting the improvement of
Philosophical Matters. Access, autonomy, and communality all serve this property right
of use, as does the sponsorship of institution and library.
The history of learning’s properties in the West, as presented in this book, spans
some 1,400 years. It has been selective and illustrative, often drawing on familiar figures
among nuns and monks, humanists and printers, masters and scholars, to bring something
afresh about how their work reflects this sense of an intellectual property. The history of
these properties has not been progressive or linear. Many of the ideas about learning were
inherited from antiquity and present in Saint Jerome. What the West brought to this work
29
with learning was different iterations of an institutional framework, from monasticism to
university and academy. If many of the people I have written about were already well-
known to me and my readers, I found myself surprised by what the scholarly literature
had to offer on what has not been told often enough about learning, involving, for
example, the philosophical and scientific debt owed to Islamic scholarship; translations
cooperative contact zone; the achievement and exclusion of women; constancy and
change in the library; learned publishings struggle with privilege, monopoly, and
censorship; the colonial consequences of a property theory.
The book may seem to end on an entirely triumphant note, with the passing of
“An Act for the Encouragement of Learning.Yet this early eighteenth-century
encouragement of learning in Britain did not yet extend to the admission of women to
higher education (with Oxford first granting women degrees in 1920), or Jews (admitted
in 1856 to Oxford), or “dissenters” from outside the Church of England (admitted in
1854), or Indians (admitted in 1871), and the list goes on. The learned did not always get
it right, or fairly, or honestly, and if I have favored the success stories here, it has been to
capture the values, as well as the cautions, in going forward. Education has always been
better about the promise and potential of improving the world than about realizing the full
extent of that improvement particularly on issues of equality of opportunity within its
own dominion. I can say that having spent my life as a school teacher and academic
involved in, as well as studying, our shortcomings in realizing our best hopes for
education. This book represents an effort to appreciate the history of what the West has
tried to make of learning through institutions and artifacts, so that we keep present the
values that have guided us in the past.
30
My principal claim for this history is that it demonstrates how much this concept
of intellectual property owes to the history of learning. Those involved in this world of
learning made the intangible qualities of texts a reality, in fact, the reality of their lives.
The learned valued texts as distinctive entities, works of labor and insight. This work
with books led to an evolving set of rights and responsibilities, institutions and
economies. Their work also managed to convince a good number of those who were not
involved in this learning of its intrinsic value to the larger world, and thus to sponsor, and
provide privileges and protections to, the study of Christian theology, the liberal arts, and
natural philosophy.
My second claim is that the work of learning creates forms of intellectual property
that stand distinctively apart from other sorts of tangible and intangible goods. It was not
that other crafts and guilds lacked intellectual property claims in what they created and
made. It is only that with learning, much of the energy and care, the development of
technique and method, is devoted to making explicit the nature and value of the
properties as intellectual. The craft of learning is in the articulation of such properties.
How could this field of learning not give substance and form to this concept of
intellectual property; how could it not be a distinct and separate form of human activity to
create such intangible goods; how could it not require its own set of privileges and
protection? As Locke felt compelled to lobby for the legislative reform of intellectual
property rights on behalf of his interests as a scholar, so this is no less of a critical time
for the encouragement of learning to rethink the legal structure of intellectual property. In
the book’s epilogue, I sketch out how a history such as this points to possible ways
forward into a digital era of greater access and utilization of research and scholarship.